17
Shakespeare, Ibsen and Plato
A
mode of understanding
Our journey is over. Through several plays we have explored
Shakespeare's views on human beings and on the relationship
between the individual and his community. We have
disregarded his language and poetry, his humour, and the
finer construction of each play in order to concentrate on
the most important parts of the content.
Great writing is formed around inner patterns. Shakespeare
disperses his rich offering through language and stories
which, taken as a whole, relate a coherent philosophy.
He lets several ways of life throw light on each other, and
compares their results. Our actions carry with them
consequences for ourselves and others, some of which are
good and others bad. Shakespeare is indefatigable in his
investigation of the relation of action to its results.
Like Plato, Spinoza and Hegel, he sees our choice of action
as decided by an ever expanding horizon that leads from the
starting point of our body and the here and now to the
future and to understanding, from isolated desire to
increasingly comprehensive communities. The solidarity of
these communities is extended right up to the international
societies that meet us in a town like Venice or in the
Europe of a visionary ruler like Henry the Fifth.
Shakespeare has in addition given us a series of thorough
studies of very complex personalities. King
Richard the Third shows a
thoroughbred psychopath; in Macbeth
we see
inner struggle, fission and repression; Timon
of Athens develops
a characterisation which avoids any hint of simple-minded
preaching on the part of the author.
People's actions and motives are mostly seen in terms of
explanations drawn from nature or society, with some light
thrown on personal background.
The sum is an understandable world. Actions receive meaning
in that some arrangements are better than others, even
though happy solutions are rare, and all are sooner or
later cancelled by death.
In the course of our discussion we examined and rejected
Jan Kott's opinion of Shakespeare as an ‘absurd’ dramatist.
There is inner consistency and meaning in Shakespeare's
plays.
Modern science uses single cases as points of departure
only, while final insights are shown through classes and
types, or through laws and forces.
Writers of fiction differ from scientists in that they
express their insight through images, characters and
stories instead of through conceptual relations and
systems. In Shakespeare's work this can be seen from the
titles of the plays as well; almost all the great tragedies
bear the protagonist's name, and so do the historic dramas.
At the same time, each destiny has received a structure of
generality, it conveys general phenomena and is made
meaningful because of this.
Strictly personal histories tend to limit the means at the
dramatist's disposal. His simplest technique is plain
juxtaposition, as when Falstaff's disgusting pranks are
directly followed by the far wider perspective opened for
young prince Hal during his dialogue with the country's
dying king. Other techniques are repetitions, miniature
plays within the play, collateral stories or revealing
conversations; but most important of all are the results
that follow from actions. The spectator can see the outcome
in full view on stage and can assess it on his own by
holding it up against his own experiences in daily life,
while the final assessment is made after criticism and
debate.
In spite of the overt differences this way of working is in
harmony with the basic attitude in the sciences and also in
moral philosophy. So are Shakespeare's individual findings;
there is consensus on the basic values which are accepted
or rejected. Literary criticism and research extract from
literature underlying themes, ideas and values and develop
them into concepts related to those of philosophy.
Myth
and ritual
Philosophy and science are not the only relevant areas of
comparison with the drama. Similar knowledge is also found
in myth, which is an early form of understanding arranged
around gods, fairies, spirits and destinies.
Versions of myths and related folk literature live on in
the theatre since the dramatist conveys his message through
stories about individuals with names. Uniting the two aims
of its teaching, viz exposing the fate of individuals and
extending its lessons to society at large, the stage
organises its personalities into types
of
characters, in the same way that chemistry classifies the
world into elements.
Another scenic precursor is ritual as part of the early
shaping of mankind, since all learning must be shared with
others, frequently repeated, and exercised in structured
ways that are met with respect. Basic religious teaching is
further safeguarded by the fact that rituals are limited to
particularly important areas: birth and death, the renewal
of the seasons, and the growth of indispensable ties and
communities, from marriage and tribe to city and class.
Thus ritual becomes a manifestation of the most fundamental
experiences of mankind, having as its aim the strengthening
of the sentiments, insights and habits without which
society cannot survive.
The theatre attends to the profane part of this task and
thus continues myth and ritual as two ancient methods of
exercising influence. Great plays survive through natural
selection. They are repeated at intervals and find their
place among other media of instruction such as church,
school, and film. The major topics are successful
solutions, on the one hand, and dangerous side tracks
leading to failure, on the other.
Background
and cause
Shakespeare often lets us understand something of the
background of his characters, especially of individuals who
are particularly vulnerable. Richard the Third is a
cripple. Iago has gone overboard on Machiavelli, while
Aaron has twice been kept back as a prisoner of war. Edgar
has the security of being born in wedlock, while Edmund is
illegitimate. Saturninus owes his throne to Titus and is
furious at being indebted to someone who insults him and
whom he suspects of striving for power indirectly.
These kinds of explanation in the plays are certainly valid
as far as they go. But Shakespeare's emphasis is never on
going back in search of a full psychological explanation of
causes; instead he looks ahead, from an action to its
effects.
In Henrik Ibsen's late plays background and revelation are
shown as one, in great simplicity. Ghosts
progressively
reveals Mrs. Alving's own guilt together with indications
of how her surroundings have previously committed
injustices against her. In the works of Shakespeare the
relationship between background, personality formation and
action never breaks through unequivocally. Instead he lets
his audience take the past for granted, while the future is
made an object of choice, based on a belief in our ability
to change through insight.
Those Shakespearean descriptions of events which do allow
us to deduce motive and cause lie mostly in the world of
adults. An important advance of the present day is the
discovery that grown people are formed from childhood. The
understanding of this is ascribed to Sigmund Freud and
psychoanalysis, while in Norway it was anticipated by
Henrik Ibsen and Knut Hamsun, immediately before Freud. The
most important contribution of the theatre came in 1858,
with Ibsen's The
Vikings at Helgeland.
Ibsen's works imply the founding of a developmental
psychology of a Freudian type. Ibsen's radical tenet in
this field, that influence from childhood determines all
later development, is clearly displayed in such characters
as Brand, Osvald of Ghosts,
Hjørdis of The
Vikings at Helgeland, and
Hedda Gabler. An important motif in most of his stories is
that the period of growth from child to adult does damage,
though with Nora of A
Doll's House a clear
exception.
Antiquity lacked a clear idea of the importance of
childhood, and so did the Renaissance. Important events in
the formative years of childhood as explanation is lacking
as a general theme in Shakespeare's plays. We can, for
instance, speculate on possible Ibsen-like interpretations
of Hamlet's behaviour on the basis of his dim past and his
apparent ambivalence towards his mother, but there is
insufficient support in Shakespeare's text for anything of
the kind.
Instead Shakespeare discusses a number of important points
of view regarding knowledge, based on a theory which stems
from Plato and which took the place of a full-fledged
developmental psychology in Shakespeare's day.
Against this background The
Tempest acquires
special importance in that Miranda expresses the author's
inkling of a whole other realm in addition to the world of
fully formed adults which he has so painstakingly
investigated. Shakespeare, however, stopped on the brink of
this new, vast field. Rather than cross the threshold, he
returned to Stratford to secure the future of his two
daughters.
Text and life
Prospero's magic in calling his assistant spirits into
action is analogous to that of his author in the theatre,
and Prospero's life echoes Shakespeare's. Shakespeare's
views on his helpers are in turn reminiscent of Ibsen's, as
expressed in his treatment of the architect and his
collaborators in The
Master Builder.
Both The
Master Builder and
The
Tempest indicate
definite spans of time corresponding to important periods
in the protagonists' lives. On Prospero's island we hear of
Ariel's having been held captive by Sycorax for twelve
years; then follow the twelve years spent by Prospero
himself on the island, with Caliban and Ariel serving him.
These 24 years find a parallel in the time spent by
Shakespeare as an actor and dramatist in London, from about
1589 to 1613. Some twelve years were devoted to comedies
and historical dramas, culminating in the transitional
plays Twelfth
Night,
Hamlet
and
As
You Like It. At the
turn of the century his production takes two different
paths: on the one hand, the completion of the sonnets,
relating the bitter story of the relationship with his
friend and of a dark lady whom the poet seems to have
loved; then follow twelve more years of the great
tragedies, and the final peace of reconciliation.
How Shakespeare himself felt the difference between the two
main periods of his life we do not know. The historical
dramas of the first twelve years have their action fixed by
outer events; while the comedies turn the foolishness of
the world upside-down with a smile, with no attempt on the
part of the author to penetrate the characters he creates.
The tragedies sharpen the conflicts. The women are victims
rather than leaders as in the comedies; both sexes have
their fates decided by their own conduct, even unto death.
The last twelve year period may perhaps have given
Shakespeare a stronger feeling of having understood the
play of life fully. All the same he regains his buoyancy
when letting Prospero, Ariel and Miranda climb back towards
the optimism of the comedies.
The change, not unexpectedly, takes place between the age
of thirty and forty. Although Shakespeare is astonishingly
mature even in his very first plays, most people seem to
experience a growing clarity in their late thirties. Ibsen
has his great visions in St. Peter's in Rome while working
on Brand;
the fully resolved plays follow from the time he turns
fifty, A
Doll's House the
turning-point. At that age the Stratford writer had retired
to await death.
The
work and its creator
Some
have doubted whether William Shakespeare could possibly be
the originator of the plays that bear his name, since the
person William Shakespeare whom we know as actor and leader
of an acting company is sloppy as regards spelling and
textual detail while the plays often show thorough insight
into natural science, law, history and psychology. This
objection may be reasonable, but another question then
follows: Who among Shakespeare's contemporaries would be a
more likely source of the plays? Any attempt to explain
richness from more limited sources is doomed to failure. At
most we may look for parallels in achievement.
A few have thought the real author of the life's work of
the poet and playwright to be the philosopher Sir Francis
Bacon. Both Bacon's writings and Shakespeare's plays
emphasise experience and new understanding drawn from
ordered patterns; but although Bacon is a considerable
thinker, there is little real similarity. Bacon strove for
social position, while Shakespeare distrusted most forms of
power. The Lord Chancellor Bacon was even charged with
bribery and dismissed — hardly in harmony with the author
of Measure
for Measure.
Furthermore, Bacon shares the Platonist rejection of
literature as wishful thinking, while England's great
writer is concerned with criticising all the
self-deceptions of everyday life, wishful thinking among
them. Francis Bacon therefore emerges a late example of the
short-sighted intellectual of antiquity; Shakespeare
exposes this personality type thoroughly in
Hamlet.
Logic
and language
The same difference is evident in their attitude to
knowledge. Both Bacon and Shakespeare analyse the world
according to Socratic definitions. But in Shakespeare's
plays, systematically elaborated characters like Iago,
Macbeth and Richard the Second are placed side by side with
other useful groupings from animate or inanimate nature;
while Bacon's lists of classifications tend to end in
fruitless truisms.
One of the reasons is that Shakespeare, in much greater
measure than Bacon, employs a Platonic logic of negation,
for example in the matter of the difference between short
term and long term goals. The consequence is a useful
analysis of reason and a fully developed critique of life,
in which each aspect of our behaviour is held up against
every other.
Hence there does not seem to be a particularly close
relationship between Shakespeare and Bacon. On the other
hand, the more we study Shakespeare, the more we come to
realise his important affinity to Plato. This is due in
part to the way in which the philosopher of antiquity, like
the Renaissance playwright, expresses himself through
conversations between named individuals. One of Plato's
most important techniques is having the participants in a
discussion give up their incorrect assumptions by showing
them how these assumptions conflict with their own
experience. Assisting him in his work are inner connections
between words, expressed through paraphrase, conceptual
categorisation and hierarchy, implication, and negation.
Against this background Plato develops the Socratic
dialogue, with its repeated clarification of the total
meaning of important statements.
Shakespeare utilises language and logic in Plato's way.
Much of the function of the fools is to provide a running
analysis of the closely related meanings of words or of
future consequences of actions, both of which their masters
may have overlooked. The clearest example is the fool
in King
Lear,
exposing old Lear's short-sightedness which makes him a
fool and not a king. A lot of the fun in the comedies has
the same basis, the interludes in the serious plays
likewise.
First and most important, there is simple word play
bringing out possible ambiguity or contrast, as when Paris
of Verona observes that “These times of woe afford no times
to woo”, or when the Capulet servants Samson and Gregory
open the play by mixing up decapitation and rape, both
involving maidens' heads.
Next, words are confused with their content. Aguecheek
in Twelfth
Night orders
the fool to sing a song beginning "Hold thy peace", but the
fool cunningly answers that if he is to be quiet he cannot
start singing!
From here the road leads to negating collocations bordering
on the poetic. Romeo describes his sadness as
not
having
that which would shorten his hours if present; Leontes and
Paulina in The
Winter's Tale speak of
the queen's kisses as treasures of a kind that leave the
giver richer in what she has given away.
The simplest version of an abstract periphrasis is to use a
substantive instead of a verb to denote action; as when
Orlando in As
You Like It says
“thou art a mocker of my labour”. The nub of all such
elaborations is the poet's sense that he is free to replace
any expression at all by infinitely many others. A clear
example is the dying John of Gaunt in King
Richard the Second who
desires to speak a word of warning to the king, hoping to
“undeaf his ear”. Quite often the plain and concrete is
described by something more general, as when the duke
in As
You Like It rephrases
rudeness as “in civility ... empty”.
The verbal manipulations and ribaldry of the fools come
close to the abuse of language and logic by the Sophists in
ancient times; but this danger, too, Shakespeare has
clearly seen. He lets the fool in Twelfth
Night speak of
words “grown so false I am loath to prove reason with
them”. The Sophists used destruction of language as a means
of dissolving the firm ground of people's lives; the fools
of the theatre instead use their own confusion as a joke or
to show us how the short-sighted calculations of the
multitude lack sense.
In spite of his obvious delight in the rich possibilities
of language, Shakespeare is like his fools: Language is
used for the purpose of clarification, not for empty
entertainment. Over time he cuts down ever more on rhyme in
his plays. Ultimately he limits himself to the splendid
rhythm of his simple blank-verse and to a use of imagery
that is made to serve the most varied of attitudes. A
comparable toning down can be found in Ibsen's writings
over the years.
None of the similarities between Shakespeare's texts and
Plato's philosophic exercises need stem from reading.
Important parts of the heritage from antiquity may have
merged with common forms of joking, or simply result from
the same kinds of heads applying themselves to the same
kind of topics.
Rationality
and consequences
The similarity between Shakespeare and Plato is everywhere.
In his most famous monologue Hamlet debates whether it is
better to suffer injustice than to commit injustice,
together with the possibility of a judgement after death —
all on the very best Platonic patterns. So too the Socratic
‘Know thyself!’ is recognisable in the reflective reasoning
of the duke in Measure
for Measure.
Basically both Plato and Shakespeare hold the view that man
is an open, impressionable mind which can be filled with
the most varied of contents.
There is further similarity in their attitudes to sensory
experience and knowledge, the moment and the future. Bacon
bases his investigations on the theory of sensation of the
atomist philosophers, like the ‘early Socrates’ of the
simplest dialogues; while Plato and Shakespeare both
distrust all purely sensory impressions deeply, even though
Shakespeare's world is more concrete than most
playwrights'. Both Plato and Shakespeare are interested in
unsuccessful experiments, and with parallel motives:
Sensations are of the instant. We accept them only because
they shut out alternative sensations from the instant which
they fill. Counter-arguments must come not from other
sensory impressions but from the intellect. As early as
in Romeo
and Juliet, the
point is formulated: “... madmen have no ears”, “... wise
men have no eyes”; the former refusing to listen to the
experience of others, the latter shutting out the
siren-song of the present and trying instead to foresee
such as is not yet visible.
Two other objections against trusting in the eye, closely
connected to the first, also unite Shakespeare and Plato:
Basing ourselves only on the limited information of the
present we can never foresee the consequences of an action
in the long term, and, secondly, it is for this reason
correspondingly easy to surrender to the perceptible
temptations of the present. Our fleeting impressions,
passions and impulses are often contradictory and offer no
solid foundation for stable relationships. Our desires last
as long as they are disappointed but cool when satisfied,
as expressed by the sensible Rosalind: “... men are April
when they woo, December when they wed.”
The image of our volatility — our ‘midsummer madness’ —
Shakespeare finds in the crescent moon of his great love
scenes, waxing and waning with our desires, and companion
to such unreasonableness as Othello killing Desdemona.
But intelligence is not in itself a sufficient guard
against the rash instability of feelings and sensations.
Shakespeare's judgement on Hamlet especially shows that he
is far from being an uncritical admirer of the intellect.
Intellectual abilities must not fossilize into academic
snobbery, or knowledge be used as a destructive or selfish
instrument. Both of these failings point to a too
restricted horizon. Acquiring a sufficiently wide overview
requires time and a sense of what may be learnt from Time.
Sophistic intelligence provides only the limited scope of
our immediate impressions. It tends to backfire, as it did
for Iago or the greedy claimants to the throne during the
civil wars. The counterpoints to Plato's sophists
Thrasymachus and Callicles are Shakespeare's Macbeth, Timon
of Athens and in part Hamlet. All such short-sighted use of
intelligence leads astray, as is most clearly exemplified
in Cleopatra among the women and Iago among the men.
In other words, Shakespeare's attitude to reason parallels
his attitude to feelings: Both must be integrated into a
lasting, meaningful framework.
The
Tempest portrays
nature as good so long as it remains undisturbed, a clear
paraphrase of Plato's belief. Captain Antonio in
Twelfth
Night says of
what appears to be a gross violation of decency and
friendship: “In nature there's no blemish but the mind”.
‘The mind’ must here be understood to refer to the
short-sighted human intelligence which can think out
perfidy in defiance of natural order, ‘nature’ to
arrangements which have passed the test of time and still
remain because they are of lasting value.
Great theatre shows all those consequences that become
clear only after a time. One of Shakespeare's clearest
confirmations of this is given towards the end of
The
Winter's Tale, where
Time appears as a prologue chorus in the fourth act: What
we shall now see “Is th'argument of Time.” The most
important contribution added by consequences is the
developmental patterns that gradually appear. The more our
consciousness grasps of the world, the better we understand
our dependence on patterns much wider than the isolated
part and the present moment.
The ‘arguments’ that Time carries in its lap are
connections that range from consequences, couples or
families, over language and class to the whole of humanity;
while the single individual, given time, finds a
corresponding completeness in his own short life. The
content of important patterns is displayed in our most
important research subjects: Natural science and philosophy
take care of the world as a whole, history investigates
peoples and mankind, the social sciences describe social
groups such as classes, and the theatre discusses the main
forms of individual life.
Philosophy,
doomsday and the theatre
There are, however, two deep differences between Plato and
Shakespeare in their attitudes to art. The ancient
philosopher has two objections to the Homeric rhapsodies:
firstly, that poetry deals only with individual cases;
secondly, that art tempts us with momentary impressions and
therefore becomes a wishful dream. Philosophy overcomes
both of these weaknesses but only through abstractions —
like the world of ideas — which make Plato doubt the
feasibility of its reaching everyone. In its place he
develops an unusual means of instruction by postulating a
life after death, with punishment and reward on the day of
judgement. This idea that our personal lives should be
extended beyond death in order for all relationships to
become manifest turns up in Hamlet,
but is otherwise of as little importance in Shakespeare's
plays as in those of Ibsen.
Instead, all great dramatists take life as seriously as
Plato took doomsday and see the same kinds of issues and
values in the light of our life on earth. Writers certainly
make use of characters and stories instead of concepts and
regularities but can on the other hand do without Plato's
world to come, since the theatre utilises simple means that
reach all spectators with a message wholly pertaining to
our present life.
In the condensed display of the stage all important
consequences can be shown during the couple of hours
available, and the theatre is the closest we come to a
purely worldly doomsday, in which well-known developments
are exhibited before the audience as judges.
Which variant we prefer is a matter of taste. The deepest
contributions of the theatre are those that are akin to
philosophy, but they can easily be overlooked by spectators
or critics who do not search for them but instead give in
to the entertainment value which good plays also have, or
to the enjoyment of the actors' performance. The sharply
defined theses of the philosophers are, on the other hand,
too abstract for many ordinary people and therefore require
the backing of religious or political wishful dreams, be it
in Rome or in Tirane.
So there is a confluence of God, thought and theatre into a
broad river. Each part of the stream has its special
river-beds and brings across content washed and purified,
but in isolation each of the three can end up in shallowly
foaming backwaters. Our richest source is found where they
merge and reinforce one another. In this sense what goes on
at the theatre concerns the totality of our lives, and all
great art is eternal.
Shakespeare took the plot of Hamlet
from an
old story in Saxo Grammaticus, Ibsen part of the figure of
Hjørdis in The
Vikings at Helgeland from the
early Germanic Volsunga saga, and Freud a different motif
from the Oedipus legend of Greek antiquity. So close is the
connection between the myths of the past and our own new
efforts. But each writer forms his clay-like material into
an original universe of his very own.
*